This is a blog to discuss philosophy, chess, politics, C. S. Lewis, or whatever it is that I'm in the mood to discuss.
Saturday, August 21, 2021
Friday, August 13, 2021
Climates of opinion
In The Problem of Pain Lewis indicated that he took
a very low view of “climates of opinion.” They do tend to shift. When I was in
college, psychology departments were dominated by behaviorists. When I was
getting my doctorate in philosophy, some 10 or so years later, the behaviorist
era was being dismissed as “the bad old days.” In biology sociobiology is still considered
debatable. In philosophy movements like Absolute Idealism, or Deconstruction, or
Logical Positivism, or Naturalized Epistemology, or Eliminative Materialism, or
Critical Race Theory, or even New Atheism, have their ups and downs.
Thursday, August 12, 2021
Good and bad reasons for restricting immigration
On what grounds do we justly restrict people from entering out country? Well, we don't want criminals, weapons, drugs, or infectious diseases coming in, so we should screen those out. If we are refusing to let people into our country because we don't want too many s****s, n*****s, and k***s in America, those are bad reasons. You'd think that would be obvious, but one of the main advisors on immigration in the last administration was an out and out white nationalism. See here.
Between the obvious good reasons, and obvious bad reasons, what reasons are valid?
Wednesday, August 11, 2021
Everything old is new again
Heard any new arguments against vaccination? Probably not. All the arguments against the COVID vaccine were used by opponents of the smallpox vaccine.
By the way, have you run into anyone lately who as contracted smallpox? How 'bout polio. Those used to be dreaded diseases. I wonder what happened to them.
Tuesday, August 10, 2021
Monday, August 02, 2021
Legal immigration
The REAL issue between me and people like Trump administration supporters is this. I think that most of who or what that tries to come over the border is benign, consisting mostly of people looking for a better life in much the way our ancestors did. Due to our prohibitive requirements for LEGAL immigration, people end up trying to come into the country illegally, and sometimes succeed and for the most part become law-abiding citizens. I have been a sub in public schools and have taught a lot of their kids. They weren't on their best behavior for me, but they are not bad kids, and they are certainly not murderers and rapists. Their undocumented parents work for a living. They should have had the opportunity to come here legally. We would need a lot less border security if we turned the ports of entry on the Southern border into little Ellis Islands instead of trying to build the Great Wall of China down there. Think about asylum seekers. They're trying to come here LEGALLY. Yeah, we would become a majority-minority country sooner, but so what? Yeah, they might need public assistance sometimes, because we let people work in America, in many cases, without paying them a living wage. This is NOT an open borders position because there still criminals, and drugs, and weapons that we need to keep out, and we would still need border security to keep those people and things out. But I think we can go a long way toward fixing illegal immigration by creating more fairness in the area of legal immigration. "Give me your tired, your poor," shouldn't just be pretty words on a statue. It's still good public policy.
Sunday, July 18, 2021
John Beversluis, 1934-2021
Admirers of C. S. Lewis were upset and very critical when John wrote "C. S. Lewis and the Search for Rational Religion." But while I strongly disagreed with his views on Lewis, he, like Socrates, asked the kinds of critical questions that people in Lewis studies were all too unwilling to raise before his book was written. His revised book on Lewis was a great improvement over the first edition. Even those who think more highly of Lewis's apologetics than he did should recognize that the study of Lewis's work is richer, not poorer for his efforts. And his writings also point the way for those who don't accept Lewis's arguments to find a great deal to appreciate, as he did.
The book was first published in 1985 by Eerdmans, a Christian publisher who had published a couple of Lewis anthologies, and later revised in 2007 for Prometheus Books, an secularist publishing house.
Thursday, July 15, 2021
On useful discussions
Discussion with intellectual opponents is something I have valued over time. Sometimes people are convinced that you are right, but not usually. Sometimes you can convince them that not everyone on your side of the issue is ignorant, stupid, insane or wicked. That's a victory not to be sneezed at. But sometimes you really end up talking to a brick wall. John Loftus, for example, started out as someone that you could have a dialogue with, and then, under the influence of New Atheism, he ceased to be one. Sometimes coming up with a realization on both sides of the issue of exactly what your disagreement consists in is a major accomplishment, even if no one is persuaded.
I am pretty much a free speech guy when it comes to these discussions, and ban people only with the greatest reluctance. Others are, to be sure, more selective.
I remember one time reading a paper that someone had written about miracles for an undergrad philosophy journal. I wrote a detailed critique of it, and then forgot all about it. Years later I heard from the person, telling me how appreciative they were of my response and that they were no a Christian.
I do think that if you cut everyone on the other side off from your discussion you lose the opportunity to be told when you are misrepresenting the other side. That's the downside. You are also out of the business of trying to show people on the other side that you are right and they are not. For me, the downsides of doing this outweigh any upsides I can think of. But that's just me.
Friday, June 25, 2021
On the belief that the other side can't be reasoned with
One philosopher and blogger that I know has indicated that he now will accept friend requests on Facebook only from those who share his conservative political views. Liberals, he says, are anti-logic and inaccessible to reason.
On the other hand, if conservatism is true, it isn't the conservatives who stand in need of persuading.
I suppose you could take that attitude on either side of the political spectrum, or the religious spectrum for that matter. On religious questions, sometimes Christians bring out Rom. 1: 18-20 to explain nonbelief.
18 The wrath of God is being revealed from heaven against all the godlessness and wickedness of people, who suppress the truth by their wickedness, 19 since what may be known about God is plain to them, because God has made it plain to them. 20 For since the creation of the world God’s invisible qualities—his eternal power and divine nature—have been clearly seen, being understood from what has been made, so that people are without excuse.
This may be true, but bringing this up to an atheist leaves you with the job of proving that it is so. Just asserting it does nothing and accomplishes less.
At the same time I have seen atheists, under the influence of the new atheists, go from fostering real discussion between themselves and believers to treating them as if they cannot be reasoned with. John Loftus is who I have in mind here.
C. S. Lewis founded the Oxford Socratic Club on the idea that Christians should open a dialogue with those who don't believe and have real discussions. In politics, I don't think American democracy can survive the conviction that the other side can't be reasoned with. Nor can it survive the widespread belief that the other side is so evil that anything done to support one's own side is OK, since the alternative is, well, the eeevil other side.
Tuesday, June 15, 2021
A Jewish Scientist Defends His Faith--and uses the argument from reason
Benjamin Fain was a Russian Jewish scientist, a dissident who worked for the welfare of Soviet Jewry. He wrote three books: Creation Ex Nihilo, (2007), Law and Providence (2011), and the Poverty of Secularism (2013). He has an interesting discussion in Creation Ex Nihilo of J. B. S. Haldane, whom crossed swords with Lewis, but whom Lewis quotes in the third chapter of Miracles.
If my mental processes are determined wholly by the motions of atoms in my brain, I have no reason for supposing that my beliefs are true. They may be sound chemically, but that does not make them sound logically. And hence I have no reason for supposing my brain to be composed of atoms. (Possible Worlds, 1927).
But he changed his mind in 1954 in "I Repent an Error."
Fain explains: The objection to his original explanation can be phrased as follows: computers act in accordance with the laws of physics, and despite this they can act in accordance with the laws of logic. The human mind can be represented by the brain, which we can compare to the computer. It is simultaneously a physical and a logical being. Out of this comes the completely materialistic explanation of the mind, or the self.
But Fain criticizes this rebuttal claiming rightly that adherence to logic is not internal to the computer itself. In the last analysis, if materialism is true, then physical laws, not logical laws, determine behavior.
JImmy Carter
Carter is often trotted out as the counterexample to the claim that personal virtue is important in selecting a President. We have seen what NOT considering personal virtue has gotten us. On the world stage he did more for world peace than any other President, and he made a serious effort to apply the teachings of Christianity to public life in a way that has not been seen before or since, including those Presidents so favored by the majority of white evangelicals.
Carter is interviewed here.
Friday, June 11, 2021
C. S. Lewis's exchanges with philosophers
Looking at the Socratic Club record, it looks as if Lewis had
memorable exchanges with four notable philosophers: C. E. M. Joad, H. H. Price,
A. J. Ayer, and Elizabeth Anscombe. The responses to Joad and Price are found
in God in the Dock. The exchange with
Ayer was in response to Ayer’s harsh critique of a paper by Michael Foster in
which Lewis took up Foster’s defense. In addition to these exchanges at the
Oxford Socratic Club, there was also the response by Lewis to a critique of his
paper on the humanitarian theory of punishment by the Australian philosopher J.
J. C. Smart. It need not be concluded that Lewis won all the other exchanges, although
Joad subsequently converted to Christianity and credited Lewis with playing an
important role in his conversion. But none of the other exchanges with
philosophers could reasonably thought of the kind of resounding defeat the
Anscombe exchange is portrayed as being. Had Lewis been as incompetent as his
is sometimes portrayed as being, it would not have taken an Anscombe to wipe
the floor with him; Joad, Price, and Ayer would have done so as well.
Thursday, June 10, 2021
God, how did you do it?
We normally ask "how" when we wonder if someone or something has the power to do something. "How did you make an A on that exam? You usually make Cs in chemistry." "How did you make that long three-point shot?" "I've been practicing for hours a day every day." Naturally if God does something, he often uses processes, and it is helpful for us who want to harness the world to learn how to do the same thing. We like mechanistic, naturalistic, "hows" because they give us blind processes that we have the power to predict and control. If we ask how did the universe come into existence where there was no universe beforehand, we are asking where the power came from to produce the universe. If "how" means "where does the power come from?" God has the power within Himself, being omnipotent.
The Ambiguities of Emergentism
Emergentism is an ambiguous idea. Does it mean that a radically different kind of causation emerges, If the laws of physics are complete (except for maybe a chance factor), and no other kind of causation is considered physicalistically acceptable, then thought that occurs in the world occurs because there is good evidence that is is true. Only blind causes, the work of the blind watchmaker, are considered scientifically acceptable. But if that's really true, then we can never, for example, believe that evolution is true because the evidence for it is good. We can only believe in evolution, or not believe in it, depending on whether the atoms in our brain happen (blindly) to put us in the positions they need to be in to believe in evolution, or whether they put us in the positions they need to be in so that we will not believe in evolution. Only physical laws an facts, not logical relationships, can be relevant to where the atoms go, and our beliefs are functions of where the atoms in our brain are at any one time. This is a description of chance-and-necessity physicalism, from Taner Edis:
Physical explanations combine rules and randomness, both of which are mindless…Hence quantum mechanics has an important role in formulating chance-and-necessity physicalism, according to which everything is physical, a combination of rule-bound and random processes, regardless of whether the most fundamental physical theory has yet been formulated…Religions usually take a top-down view, starting with an irreducible mind to shape the material world from above. Physicalism, whatever form it takes, supports a bottom-up understanding of the world, where life and mind are the results of complex interactions of fundamentally mindless components.
Taner
Edis, “Arguments Involving Cosmology and Quantum Physics,” in Joseph M. Koterski
and Graham Oppy ed., Theism and Atheism:
Opposing Arguments in Philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 2019), pp. 599-600.
Sunday, June 06, 2021
The Groundhog Day Massacre
The Anscombe-Lewis exchange took place on Feb. 2, 1948, Groundhog Day. I can see a movie about the two participants repeating the exchange over and over with different results. But Andie McDowell as Anscombe is a stretch. And Bill Murray as C. S. Lewis???
Lucas's Godelian argument against materialism
I had the chance to meet Lucas at a Wheaton Conference in, I think, 1989.
Apparently, Godel reached the same conclusion in his Gibbs lecture of 1951, but it never came out until 1995.
J. R. Lucas's treatment of The Abolition of Man
Among students of C. S. Lewis J. R. Lucas is known as the philosopher who took Lewis's part in a re-run debate some 21 years later with Elizabeth Anscombe, and who was generally thought to have gotten the better of the discussion.
Here is his paper on Lewis.
Thursday, May 27, 2021
Skeptical Threats and Best Explanations
I distinguish between what I call skeptical threat arguments, which assume that we have the faculties we have but then say that theism, not naturalism, can answer skeptical questions we might raise about them, and best explanation arguments, where the argument is that it is rational inference is a reality that neither theist nor naturalist is inclined to deny, and then goes on to argue that if the naturalistic ontology is all there is, rational inference either cannot happen or is unlikely to happen. Bill Hasker thought I should call these arguments transcendental arguments rather than best explanation arguments, and I think he's right. Rational inference requires intentionality (aboutness), truth, mental causation in virtue of mental content, the existence of logical laws, the psychological relevance of those laws, the identity of a real person throughout the process of a rational inference, and the reliability of our rational faculties. Yet, according to most modern naturalists, the physical realm is the basic reality, it's causally closed, and at that basic level there is no intentionality (about-ness), no first-person perspective, no purpose, and no normativity. Whatever else exists has to supervene on that, and to me that means the mental has to be epiphenomenal. Naturalists respond back that in making this argument I am committing the fallacy of composition, in that what isn't true at the basic level might be true at the "system" level. But, really, to allow for rational inference you have to allow a kind of causation (for example, teleological) that is disallowed at the physical level, and if all causation is really physical causation, then how can there be mental causation on any level? Furthermore, rational inference requires that we perceive implications. But implications do not exist at any particular location in space and time, so how could we perceive them if we are purely space-time bound physical creatures.
Wednesday, May 26, 2021
Distinguishing two theses in Anscombe's reply to C. S. Lewis
From an essay I am writing on the Anscombe legend.
Now
most of Anscombe’s argumentation is aimed at establishing what I will call
thesis A:
A) The argument Lewis presents in the third chapter of
the first edition of Miracles overlooks
some crucial distinctions, and therefore fails to show that naturalism is
incompatible with the validity of reasoning.
However, at the end of her piece Anscombe goes on to
say the following:
I
do not think that there is sufficiently good reason for maintaining the
“naturalist” hypothesis about human behaviour and thought. But someone who does
maintain it cannot be refuted as you try to refute him, by saying that it is
inconsistent to maintain it and to believe that human reasoning is valid and
that human reasoning sometimes produces human opinion.
In other words she
asserts what I will call thesis B:
B) You cannot refute the naturalist position by saying his position is inconsistent to say that naturalism is true, that human reasoning is valid, and that humans reasoning sometimes produces human opinion.
This goes beyond
saying that Lewis didn’t refute
naturalism because he overlooked the distinctions Anscombe insisted upon, this
is to say that you can’t refute the naturalist on the basis of the validity of
reasoning, because of these distinctions.
Did Lewis concur with A? Almost
certainly he did. I have known some philosophers who have thought that Lewis
really didn’t need to revise his chapter at all, including the late philosopher
Richard Purtill, but Lewis did not concur. (Neither would I). Even in his initial brief response to
Anscombe’s critique, which was published in the same issue of the Socratic
Digest in which her essay appeared, he acknowledged the difficulty surrounding
the use of the term “valid” and employed one of Anscombe’s central
distinctions, between the cause and effect because, and what he called the ground and consequent because. He
indicated in his reply to Norman Pittenger that the third chapter of Miracles contained
a “serious hitch” and that it “needs to be rewritten.” Establishing A is a good
day’s work for a philosopher, particularly in that she persuaded the very
person to whom she was responding that one of his central arguments, as stated,
had serious problems and needed to be reworked.
Now, if this is what winning the
debate amounts to, Anscombe won, and Lewis agreed that she did. But she did go
on to assert B, and if winning the debate requires establishing B, Lewis
dissented. He wrote in his short response in the Socratic Digest:
It
would seem, therefore, that we never think the conclusion because GC it is the
consequent of its grounds but only because CE certain previous events have
happened. If so, it does not seem that the GC sequence makes us more likely to
think the true conclusion than not. And this is very much what I meant by the
difficulty in Naturalism.
Lewis would go on
to make this claim the centerpiece of his argument when he revised the chapter.
He wrote:
But even if grounds do exist, what exactly have
they got to do with the actual occurrence of the belief as a psychological
event? If it is an event it must be caused. It must in fact be simply one link
in a causal chain which stretches back to the beginning and forward to the end
of time. How could such a trifle as lack of logical grounds prevent the
belief’s occurrence or how could the existence of grounds promote it?
I am inclined to be
resistant to talking about winning and losing in philosophical debates. They
are not football games. The Christian
philosopher and apologist William Lane Craig often does public debates on
apologetical issues, and usually comes out looking better than his opponents.
But skeptics have complained, with some justification, that doing well in a
public debate format is not the same as proving one’s central thesis to be true
from a philosophical standpoint. Now, if we are going to assess a winner in the
exchange, there are, as Bassham notes a few different ways this can be
assessed. Do we look just at the exchange on that day in at the Oxford Socratic
Club, or do we look at the overall exchange between the two parties over time?
Do we go by what the audience thought had happened? In a couple of important
senses, Anscombe was the clear winner, especially if you look only at what
happened on Feb. 2, 1948. There is no reason to doubt Carpenter’s report that
many in the audience thought that a conclusive blow had been struck against one
of Lewis’s fundamental arguments. On the narrow question of whether Lewis’s
formulation of the argument is philosophically adequate, Anscombe contended
that it wasn’t, and Lewis agreed. However, the most interesting philosophical
question of whether or not you can refute naturalism based on the validity of
reasoning cannot be settled the outcome of a particular exchange at a debating
club. When Walter Hooper asked Lewis if he said he lost the debate with
Anscombe, and Lewis said he didn’t, Lewis was probably thinking in terms of the
question of whether Anscombe had shown that B is true. He was convinced that
she had not. And looking at Anscombe’s responses to Lewis’s revised work, both
in the introduction to her collected papers, and in her longer response given
to the Oxford C. S. Lewis Society in 1985, she does not reassert B. So far as I
can tell from her responses, she does not think that Lewis had established that
B is false, but she no longer confidently asserted that B is true. I would
summarize this by saying that I think Anscombe won a significant, but only
partial, victory, and in this I believe Lewis would concur.
Thursday, May 20, 2021
Did C. S. Lewis come to think that Christian Apologetics is a Misguided Enterprise?
The Anscombe incident is often trotted
out as an object lesson for those foolish enough to engage in Christian
apologetics. An example of this comes from Ruth Tucker, a Christian
author from Calvin Theological Seminary who uses the Anscombe incident as part
of her critique of Christian apologetics and defense of fideism. Tucker thinks
it was a good thing that Lewis left some of his apologetics behind and came to
the foot of the cross, taking the line that Lewis gave up apologetics for,
mostly children’s fantasy tales, after the Anscombe incident. She thinks this was good because apologetics
is an enterprise that renders the Christian intellectually arrogant and
domineering (and, of course, we all love Narnia). She does note that Lewis
revised his chapter to repair the “serious hitch” that Anscombe had revealed
(something not usually mentioned by those who use the Anscombe incident to
prove some anti-apologetic point), but seems not to ask the question of why
anyone would bother to revise an apologetic argument if they had been persuaded
that this argument was simply bad, or that arguments for God don’t work, or that
apologetics is a bad idea. In fact Lewis wrote lots of fiction prior to the
Anscombe incident, and plenty of apologetics after it,
She
chides me as someone who defends Lewis’s original argument (I don’t, I defend
his revised argument, with amendments), and she thinks it telling that I wasn’t
able to persuade my dissertation committee that my argument was a good one. Hers
seems to be a version of the argument against the apologetic enterprise that
says, “Well, these arguments don’t persuade people, so why spend time on them?”
But
anyone who spends time in secular academic circles knows that one can be made
to feel that Christianity, or even theism, is a nonstarter and that everyone is
entitled to simply assume its claims are false. I remember a friend of mine
once telling me about a philosophy professor who told his students “Let me clue
you in. There’s no God.” Many discussions in the philosophy of mind take
materialism for granted as a basic assumption. Encountering this, as many do, I
asked whether this was the result of overwhelming evidence, of whether there were
deep and serious problems with atheistic materialism toward which Lewis was
pointing. Studying the argument in grad school (it took me awhile to be fully
convinced), I concluded that the latter was true. I’ve never assumed that the
case for Christianity is necessarily going to overwhelm people, or even to
provide absolute certainty for the believer, but rather that, at the end of the
day, there are good enough reasons for reasonable people to conclude that
Christian theism provides the most adequate understanding of the world. If
people are persuaded that intelligent people don’t accept Christian beliefs,
then faith tends to suffocate. Austin Farrer put it very nicely in his essay on
Lewis as an apologist.
It is commonly said that if rational argument is
so seldom the cause of conviction, philosophical apologists must largely be
wasting their shot. The premise is true, but the conclusion does not follow.
For though argument does not create conviction, the lack of it destroys belief.
What seems to be proved may not be embraced; but what no one shows the ability
to defend is quickly abandoned. Rational argument does not create belief, but
it maintains a climate in which belief may flourish. So the apologist who does
nothing but defend may play a useful, though preparatory, part.